Thinking Catherine Malabou
eBook - ePub

Thinking Catherine Malabou

Passionate Detachments

Thomas Wormald, Isabell Dahms

Share book
  1. 272 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Thinking Catherine Malabou

Passionate Detachments

Thomas Wormald, Isabell Dahms

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This volume contributes to the growing body of literature exploring the work of contemporary French philosopher Catherine Malabou. Through its fifteen contributions, including two previously untranslated essays by Malabou, the volume explores the various ways in which Malabou's thought both performs and furnishes resources for the negotiation of philosophy's attachment and detachment from itself and other disciplines. What kind of interaction can philosophy have with either science or politics without conquering them? How does one carry out philosophy while subverting it, changing it, directing it on or opening it up to different pathways? The chapters explore the detachment of Malabou from her own philosophical training in deconstruction, the theme of habit and the question of new attachments, detachments through the relation of Malabou's thought and science, and the detachments that transpire through philosophy's confrontation with politics. In order to have a future, philosophy must detach from its own tradition and passionately confront questions of race, gender, and colonialism.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Thinking Catherine Malabou an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Thinking Catherine Malabou by Thomas Wormald, Isabell Dahms in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Deconstruction in Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Section 1

Detaching from Derrida?

The Future of Deconstruction after Malabou

Chapter 1

Is Science the Subject of Philosophy? Miller, Badiou, and Derrida Respond1

Catherine Malabou
Translated by William Samson
I wish to make you aware of two reading experiences I have had. The first is that of reading Alain Badiou’s 1969 text, published in Cahiers pour l’analyse, titled “Mark and Lack,” where we can find the affirmation that gave rise to my title: “Science is the subject of philosophy.”2 This chapter is a response to Jacques Alain Miller’s “Suture: Elements of the Logic of the Signifier,”3 published a few years prior to Badiou’s essay in the same journal. Despite their specific and very dated context—their questions about science had to confront, in that time, both psychoanalysis and Marxism—they contain very important elements for thinking the relations between science and philosophy today, and they have import that, in my opinion, goes well beyond their time.
The second discovery is altogether different. While, for other reasons, I was recently rereading Derrida’s “Passions: An Oblique Offering,”4 I was struck by the coincidence—if not the similarity—of the analyses developed in that book with those developed by Badiou about the situation of philosophy. The word “situation” is being taken here in its proper sense, as venue, place, and orientation, all at the same time. This coincidence is more surprising given that the two thinkers have little in common with each other, as is attested to by the extreme difference in the points of departure of their respective discourses. Badiou undertakes the analysis of the relations between philosophy and mathematical logic, while Derrida concerns himself with the relations between philosophy and literature. Despite it all, their conclusions strangely and mutually echo each other.
In both cases, what I will call the law of the fault of philosophy (la loi du défaut de philosophie) emerges. For both thinkers, philosophy is in need of an answer. It wants to answer for everything, even, which is the problem, for that which does not respond. What does not respond, for Badiou, is science. For Derrida, literature. Examining these two types of nonresponses more closely will constitute my subject, which is precisely the question of the subject. There is no subject of science, says Badiou; there is no subject of literature, says Derrida. This double absence of subject constitutes precisely, for them, the subject of philosophy, which is supposed to respond in their place by wrongly characterizing this absence as a lack. A lack which it is possible not to fill, but at least to make speak.
* * *
Let us start with Miller. He undertakes to show that science, and in particular mathematical logic, proceeds from a denial of lack, and sutures closed all that could leave the place of the other of science (which is to say, the subject-function) empty. By definition, science is “objective” and admits no lacuna or void, no desire nor gap. This constitutes the “suture” or foreclosure that Miller, with the help of Lacan, intends to deconstruct. To this end, Miller begins with a reading of Frege’s The Foundations of Arithmetic, where he defends the idea that zero, in mathematics, is precisely not a void or a lack.5 Miller will then demonstrate that zero in reality marks the place of the subject’s foreclosure.
In The Foundations of Arithmetic, Frege defines number. A number refers to no particular thing. It does, however, have an object. What is the difference between a thing—that empirical X—and an object? The difference between four balls as things and what the number 4 measures? What do things become once they are numbered and numerable, in other words? They become units. Because of this, they obey particular syntactic determinations, which are ordered by a fundamental rule or structure, which Frege outlines in the following way: Numbers are extensions of concepts. The number 4, for example, is the extension of the concept “four.” The two are equinumerical. “The number which belongs to the concept F,” says Frege, “is the extension of the concept ‘equinumerical to the concept F.’ ”6
What does “concept” mean here? “Concept” signifies self-identity. Saying that a number is an extension of a concept signifies that a number is identical to its concept, that it is identical to itself. In other words, as Miller rightly says, all numbers presuppose “the concept of identity to a concept.”7 This rule of identity to a concept is valid for all numbers. “The concept of identity to a concept” works for every number. This is the rule of unity: being self-identical means to “be one.” There is thus some “one” in all numbers. “This one [that of the singular unit] … is common to all numbers in so far as they are first constituted as units.”8
The object is the thing become one (self-identical), and thus numberable. “That definition, pivotal to his concept,” continues Miller, “is one that Frege borrows from Leibniz. It is contained in this statement: eadem sunt quorum unum potest substitui alteri salva veritate. Those things are identical of which one can be substituted for the other salva veritate without loss of truth.”9 Numbers are substitutable for one another insofar as in them, at any time, the self-identical repeats itself, that is, the “one” of the unit. We can thus “pass” from one number to another without losing truth, since identity is preserved.
But the problem then arises of knowing how one “progresses” from one number to another. How the number can “pass from the repetition of the 1 of the identical to its ordered succession: 1, 2, 3, 4, 5?” The answer is for that to occur, “the zero has to appear.”10 And Miller here makes reference to the very influential Fregian analysis of zero.
Why is the “engendering of the zero”11 necessary for Frege? At this point, we’ve posited the self-identity of the concept of number, and thus of the number itself. That’s to say that “non-identity with itself is contradictory to the very dimension of truth.” How then to designate nonidentity? “To its concept, we assign the zero,” says Miller, reading Frege. Nothing falls under the concept “nonidentical with itself” if not, Miller continues, a void or a gap. Zero is the name of that nothing. Yet Frege defines zero as a number, to which he assigns the cardinal 1. This is where the “suture” comes from, from that eclipse of the zero by the one.
The non–self-identical answers fully, for Frege, to the principle by which, for any object, it must be possible to say under what concept it must be subsumed. Yet zero can be subsumed under the concept of non-self-identity as “identical to zero.” Thus, zero is identical to its concept, the concept of non-self-identity. Let there be a concept “identical to zero.” One and only one object, zero, is subsumed under that concept. “One” is thus by definition the cardinal number that belongs to that concept. Zero is “one” in the sense of self-identity. Now, in trying to make the number 1 appear, it must be shown that something can immediately follow zero in the series of natural numbers. “Zero,” Miller says, following Frege, “is the number assigned to the non-self-identical. This number is 1 [marked zero]. It follows that 1 follows immediately from 0 in the series of natural numbers.”12 And from there we can deduce the set of numbers, following the structure of “following from,” with the restriction that no number can follow itself in the natural series of numbers beginning with zero. Inscribing zero as a point of departure for the series of numbers makes it possible that the rule n + 1: 0 (self-identity of the concept “not identical to itself”) is followed by 1, which itself is followed by 2, then by 3, and so on.
Examining the Fregean argument, Miller concludes that the zero is at the same time summoned and dismissed. “That which in the real is pure and simple absence finds itself through the fact of number (through the instance of truth) noted 0 and counted for 1.”13 The word “suture” signifies (1) the uniting, by use of thread, of divided parts after an accident or surgical intervention and (2) the immobile articulation characterized by two jointed surfaces united by fibrous tissue, like those which from the cranium, the apparent line constituting the conjunction of two parts. The suture is thus always at the same time a division and conjunction. In every case, the seam, the conjunction, remains visible.
What is really sutured in Frege’s discourse in particular and in formal scientific language in general? Miller responds: the subject-function. “To designate it I choose the name of suture. Suture names the relation of the subject to the chain of its discourse.”14 The appearance-disappearance of the zero in the series of numbers figures the appearance-disappearance of the subject in the chain of its discourse.
Frege affirms, however, multiple times that logic does not follow from a subjective act, which is always psychological. Yet it is precisely this which appears to Miller as a denial. According to Frege, the subject counts for nothing. From this, it follows that suturing the zero can be read as suturing the subject. Indeed, for Miller, only the subject-function can subtend the operations of abstraction, of unification, and of progression. There is, therefore, identity only for a subject. It is the subject that produces the primary unity; it is impossible to think self-identity outside of the subject, since the subject-function is the identity-function. We’ve known since Descartes that a subject is, by definition, a power identical to itself. The subject is the form of identity. At the same time, like the zero, the subject is never self-identical. Like the zero, it receives its identity from a lack, it misses itself. The relationship of the zero to the chain of numbers is the same as the relationship of the subject to the chain of discourse. Like the zero, the subject is both present and absent at once. “It figures [in the chain] as the element which is lacking, in the form of a stand-in. For, while there lacking, it is not purely and simply absent.”15 Lacan shows that, in the same way that the zero is excluded from the beginning from the chain of numbers, the subject is excluded from the field of the Other, which is what comes to bar the subject. The subject displaces this bar onto the A, “a displacement whose effect is the emergence of signification signified to the subject.”16 Yet “untouched by the exchange of the bar, this exteriority of the subject to the Other is maintained, which institutes the unconscious.”17 The summation of the subject in the field of the other calls for its annulment.18 The subject, in this way, is always alienated from and by the very process of its signification.
Regarding Frege, we have spoken of (1) unity and (2) the role of 0 in succession, its status as number, and finally of its eclipse by the 1. This structure of appearance-disappearance, of suture, would be the point, emergent or derived, of a more originary logic which Miller, with Lacan’s help, proposes to name the “logic of the signifier”—a logic that proposes to “make itself known as a logic at the origin of logic,”19 which retraces the steps of logic, a “retroaction,”20 or a repression. “What is it that functions in the series of whole natural numbers to which we can assign their progression? And the answer, which I shall give at once before establishing it: in the process of the constitution of the series, in the genesis of progression, the function of the subject, miscognized, is operative.”21 Zero is the placeholder of the subject, which is itself, insofar as...

Table of contents