Heidegger
eBook - ePub

Heidegger

John Richardson

Partager le livre
  1. 408 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (adapté aux mobiles)
  4. Disponible sur iOS et Android
eBook - ePub

Heidegger

John Richardson

DĂ©tails du livre
Aperçu du livre
Table des matiĂšres
Citations

À propos de ce livre

Martin Heidegger is one of the twentieth century's most influential, but also most cryptic and controversial philosophers. His early fusion of phenomenology with existentialism inspired Sartre and many others, and his later critique of modern rationality inspired Derrida and still others. This introduction covers the whole of Heidegger's thought and is ideal for anyone coming to his work for the first time.

John Richardson centres his account on Heidegger's persistent effort to change the very kind of understanding or truth we seek. Beginning with an overview of Heidegger's life and work, he sketches the development of Heidegger's thought up to the publication of Being and Time. He shows how that book takes up Husserl's method of phenomenology and adapts it. He then introduces and assesses the key arguments of Being and Time under three headings—pragmatism, existentialism, and temporality—its three levels of analysis of human experience.

Subsequent chapters introduce Heidegger's later philosophy, including his turn towards a historical account of being, and new ideas about how we need to 'think' to get the truth about it; his influential writings on language, art, and poetry, and their role in the Western history of being; and his claim that this history has culminated in a technological relation to things that is deeply problematic, above all in the way it excludes the divine. The final chapter looks at Heidegger's profound influence on several intellectual movements ranging from phenomenology to existentialism to postmodernism.

A much-needed and refreshing introduction to this major figure, Heidegger is ideal reading for anyone coming to his work for the first time and will interest and stimulate students and scholars alike.

Foire aux questions

Comment puis-je résilier mon abonnement ?
Il vous suffit de vous rendre dans la section compte dans paramĂštres et de cliquer sur « RĂ©silier l’abonnement ». C’est aussi simple que cela ! Une fois que vous aurez rĂ©siliĂ© votre abonnement, il restera actif pour le reste de la pĂ©riode pour laquelle vous avez payĂ©. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Puis-je / comment puis-je télécharger des livres ?
Pour le moment, tous nos livres en format ePub adaptĂ©s aux mobiles peuvent ĂȘtre tĂ©lĂ©chargĂ©s via l’application. La plupart de nos PDF sont Ă©galement disponibles en tĂ©lĂ©chargement et les autres seront tĂ©lĂ©chargeables trĂšs prochainement. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Quelle est la différence entre les formules tarifaires ?
Les deux abonnements vous donnent un accĂšs complet Ă  la bibliothĂšque et Ă  toutes les fonctionnalitĂ©s de Perlego. Les seules diffĂ©rences sont les tarifs ainsi que la pĂ©riode d’abonnement : avec l’abonnement annuel, vous Ă©conomiserez environ 30 % par rapport Ă  12 mois d’abonnement mensuel.
Qu’est-ce que Perlego ?
Nous sommes un service d’abonnement Ă  des ouvrages universitaires en ligne, oĂč vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  toute une bibliothĂšque pour un prix infĂ©rieur Ă  celui d’un seul livre par mois. Avec plus d’un million de livres sur plus de 1 000 sujets, nous avons ce qu’il vous faut ! DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Prenez-vous en charge la synthÚse vocale ?
Recherchez le symbole Écouter sur votre prochain livre pour voir si vous pouvez l’écouter. L’outil Écouter lit le texte Ă  haute voix pour vous, en surlignant le passage qui est en cours de lecture. Vous pouvez le mettre sur pause, l’accĂ©lĂ©rer ou le ralentir. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Est-ce que Heidegger est un PDF/ePUB en ligne ?
Oui, vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  Heidegger par John Richardson en format PDF et/ou ePUB ainsi qu’à d’autres livres populaires dans Philosophy et Philosophy History & Theory. Nous disposons de plus d’un million d’ouvrages Ă  dĂ©couvrir dans notre catalogue.

Informations

Éditeur
Routledge
Année
2012
ISBN
9781136460470
Seven
Heidegger’s turning
Famously, Heidegger undergoes a “turning” [Kehre] in the decade after Being and Time, a change in the basic direction or orientation of his thinking. The term is Heidegger’s own; he applies it to a sig-nificant shift he retrospectively sees in himself. And indeed many changes are obvious from even superficial comparisons of that book with the later essays. We enter a distinctly different world in the latter, and must adjust ourselves to meet it.
I should say at the outset that the crux of the turning—what it was from and to—is open to debate; there have been rather different accounts of it. Heidegger himself offers, during this turning itself, no direct statement of what it amounts to, and only a few later accounts.1 So I’ll be giving a reading of it, not stating an obvious fact.
It is also debatable just when the turning occurs. I will take it to be during the latter half of the 1930s. Contributions to Philosophy [1936–38] is the most thorough statement of the emerging new view. But there are anticipations of it in the early 1930s, and I will also use these texts in treating his “later” view. Moreover, we will see that the turn doesn’t arrive at a stable position. Heidegger pivots, and continues to pivot: all the rest of his career can be seen as a progressive turning. He steadily radicalizes his critique of the position he turns away from, so that his initial accounts of the turn come to be seen as incomplete and misleading.
The main philosophical influences on this turn are Nietzsche and Hölderlin; they clarified the direction he already wanted to go. Very broadly—and of course there are many exceptions to this—the turn is towards Hölderlin and against Nietzsche.
Heidegger turns from Nietzsche, seen as giving key statement to the modern stance, and looming behind the aspects of Being and Time he now wants to renounce. That book’s pragmatic and existential themes are still Nietzschean: they express the spirit Nietzsche framed in his ontology of will to power, and in his lesson that man should take the place of the dead God as master of all. And this Nietzschean spirit is also linked with Heidegger’s—and Germany’s—political and moral error in embracing Hitler.
So the turn also has this biographical side: it is Heidegger’s philosophical response to his unhappy experience with National Socialism. He never explicitly says this. Indeed I think he actively suppresses it, in his stubborn defense of his behavior in the Nazi years. (This also leads him, at times, to understate the turning by reading later views back into Being and Time.) But to an extent—that we will need to determine—this turning amounts to an acknowledgment of error, in the place that counts most to him, his core thinking about being.
The turn towards Hölderlin expresses, by contrast, a religious revival in Heidegger. He takes over Hölderlin’s idea that the secular philosophy of human will expresses an age in which gods are absent—an absence we must properly regret. We need to look and prepare towards their return, in some new religiousness whose vocabulary he begins to construct. That this return to religion need not be to Christianity, however, we can gather from his adoption of Hölderlin’s polytheism. It is this new positive aim that explains his changed discursive method and style. His later writing is often more “poetic” or “literary,” and tends to renounce the quasi-Cartesian method of Being and Time, as well as its Kantian system.
I’ll discuss Heidegger’s “late” views in this and the following two chapters. In this one I’ll try to clarify the turning itself: to identify the fundamental changes that occur after Being and Time. This will involve presenting an outline of his late position—which of course chiefly concerns being, and how it is concealed and unconcealed. His views about “language and art” (Chapter 8) and “technology and gods” (Chapter 9) will then be grounded in these central claims.
Since Heidegger’s “later” writings extend over several decades, and since (as said) he continues to turn or pivot all through them, a really thorough account would need to be chronological. I will have to compress much of this development in order to present his position in its large-scale argumentative structure—though I will point out some of the stages as we go.
As I’ll try to show, the main lesson of this overall shift is, once again, in the kind of understanding Heidegger thinks philosophers—and all of us—need. He radicalizes the critique he had already made against the usual epistemic aim of a theoretical-conceptual grasp of the at-hand. He broadens his target so that it now includes the pragmatic-existential understanding that Being and Time itself had pursued. His later writings push this lesson ever further, so that the kind of understanding we need is more and more different from all that is usual to us.
For Heidegger’s later view there is no single dominant work—no book in which he gives detailed statement to the full range of his new ideas, as he had done in Being and Time. His interpreters’ regret at this absence showed in the long anticipation and then reception of a “secret work” written 1936–39, just after his turning: Contributions to Philosophy: From Ereignis (often referred to as “the BeitrĂ€ge”). This was long rumored his second magnum opus, and was so greeted by many when it was finally published in 1989. It is of great interest, and I will use it often in this chapter. But it (1) is mostly in very rough order, and (2) lacks the density, the thoughtthrough detail, that characterizes Being and Time. There is no second “great work,” and no comprehensive statement of Heidegger’s view “after the turn.” We will for the most part be looking at essays with narrower ambitions—though insofar as all of them try to speak of being (and Ereignis), they have (Heidegger thinks) the very highest ambition.
1. Character of the turn
I start with an overview of the new position, to show how the detailed accounts to follow will hang together. Here my aim is to show the position only schematically; many of these ideas will need to be both motivated, and understood rather differently than it might in this first telling seem (since some of the terms will need special senses). These ideas will also need to be “brought to life” out of this preliminary and flattening sketch, which little tries to give the very kind of understanding Heidegger will insist on. Still I think it will be helpful to start with a large-scale map.
Let’s start with what doesn’t change. Heidegger still holds that being [Sein] is the important topic: it is what we should all be paying most attention to, but that we’re sadly, predictably neglecting. His main ambition as a philosopher is to bring himself and his readers into a proper relation to it, into the “truth of being.” This gist is already in Being and Time, and Heidegger stresses it all the more emphatically as he goes. He adopts more and more the prophet’s role: calling us back to this proper attention to being, from our misguided preoccupation with things and one another.
But as Heidegger goes on he treats this problem of being as harder and harder; this is the gist of the turning. Over and over he will suggest a way to state the difference of being from entities, which then a few years later turns out still to fall short of it, requiring yet another new formulation. This progressive radicalizing eventually impinges on the very word “being,” and Heidegger adopts a series of other locutions for what he means, such as the antique Seyn, and writing Sein with a cross-out superimposed.
What is it in Being and Time that gets left behind? As we’ve seen, one key way that boo...

Table des matiĂšres