Texts by Arendt
From The Life of the Mind, Volume One
IN THE SECOND VOLUME of this work [The Life of the Mind] I shall deal with willing and judging, the two other mental activities. Looked at from the perspective of these time speculations, they concern matters that are absent either because they are not yet or because they are no more; but in contradistinction to the thinking activity, which deals with the invisibles in all experience and always tends to generalize, they always deal with particulars and in this respect are much closer to the world of appearances. If we wish to placate our common sense, so decisively offended by the need of reason to pursue its purposeless quest for meaning, it is tempting to justify this need solely on the grounds that thinking is an indispensable preparation for deciding what shall be and for evaluating what is no more. Since the past, being past, becomes subject to our judgment, judgment, in turn, would be a mere preparation for willing. This is undeniably the perspective, and, within limits, the legitimate perspective, of man insofar as he is an acting being.
But this last attempt to defend the thinking activity against the reproach of being impractical and useless does not work. The decision the will arrives at can never be derived from the mechanics of desire or the deliberations of the intellect that may precede it. The will is either an organ of free spontaneity that interrupts all causal chains of motivation that would bind it or it is nothing but an illusion. In respect to desire, on one hand, and to reason, on the other, the will acts like âa kind
of coup dâĂ©tat,â as Bergson once said, and this implies, of course, that âfree acts are exceptionalâ: âalthough we are free whenever we are willing to get back into ourselves,
it seldom happens that we are willing.â
1 In other words, it is impossible to deal with the willing activity without touching on the problem of freedom.
[
Three paragraphs of the original text, pertaining to the account of willing in volume two of
The Life of the Mind, are omitted here.âR.B.]
I shall conclude the second volume with an analysis of the faculty of judgment, and here the chief difficulty will be the curious scarcity of sources providing authoritative testimony. Not till Kantâs Critique of Judgment did this faculty become a major topic of a major thinker.
I shall show that my own main assumption in singling out judgment as a distinct capacity of our minds has been that judgments are not arrived at by either deduction or induction; in short, they have nothing in common with logical operationsâas when we say: All men are mortal, Socrates is a man, hence, Socrates is mortal. We shall be in search of the âsilent sense,â whichâwhen it was dealt with at allâhas always, even in Kant, been thought of as âtasteâ and therefore as belonging to the realm of aesthetics. In practical and moral matters it was called âconscience,â and conscience did not judge; it told you, as the divine voice of either God or reason, what to do, what not to do, and what to repent of. Whatever the voice of conscience may be, it cannot be said to be âsilent,â and its validity depends entirely upon an authority that is above and beyond all merely human laws and rules.
In Kant judgment emerges as âa peculiar talent which can be practiced only and cannot be taught.â Judgment deals with particulars, and when the thinking ego moving among generalities emerges from its withdrawal and returns to the world of particular appearances, it turns out that the mind needs a new âgiftâ to deal with them. âAn obtuse or narrow-minded person,â Kant believed, â. . . may indeed be trained through study, even to the extent of becoming learned. But as such people are commonly still lacking in judgment, it is not unusual to meet learned men who in the application of their scientific knowledge betray that original want, which can never be made good.â
2 In Kant, it is reason with its âregulative ideasâ that comes to the help of judgment; but if the faculty is separate from other faculties of the mind, then we shall have to ascribe to it its own
modus operandi, its own way of proceeding.
And this is of some relevance to a whole set of problems by which modern thought is haunted, especially to the problem of theory and practice and to all attempts to arrive at a halfway plausible theory of ethics. Since Hegel and Marx, these questions have been treated in the perspective of History and on the as
sumption that there is such a thing as Progress of the human race. Finally we shall be left with the only alternative there is in these matters. Either we can say with Hegel:
Die Weltgeschichte ist das Weltgericht, leaving the ultimate judgment to Success, or we can maintain with Kant the autonomy of the minds of men and their possible independence of things as they are or as they have come into being.
Here we shall have to concern ourselves, not for the first time,
3 with the concept of history, but we may be able to reflect on the oldest meaning of this word, which, like so many other terms in our political and philosophical language, is Greek in origin, derived from
historein, âto inquire in order to tell how it wasââ
legein ta eonta in Herodotus. But the origin of this verb is in turn Homer (
Iliad XVIII), where the noun
histĆr (âhistorian,â as it were) occurs, and that Homeric historian is the
judge. If judgment is our faculty for dealing with the past, the historian is the inquiring man who by relating it sits in judgment over it. If that is so, we may reclaim our human dignity, win it back, as it were, from the pseudo-divinity named History of the modern age, without denying historyâs importance but denying its right to be the ultimate judge. Old Cato, with whom I started these reflectionsââNever am I less alone than when I am by myself, never am I more active than when I do nothingââhas left us a curious phrase, which aptly sums up the political principle implied in the enterprise of reclamation. He said: â
Victrix causa deis placuit, sed victa Catoniâ (âThe victorious cause pleased the gods, but the defeated one pleases Catoâ).
Lectures on Kantâs Political Philosophy Delivered at the New School For Social Research, Fall, 1970
First Session
TO TALK ABOUT and inquire into Kantâs political philosophy has its difficulties. Unlike so many other philosophersâPlato, Aristotle, Augustine, Thomas, Spinoza, Hegel, and othersâhe never wrote a political philosophy. The literature on Kant is enormous, but there are very few books on his political philosophy, and, of these, there is only one that is worth studyingâHans Sanerâs
Kants Weg vom Krieg zum Frieden.
1 In France there appeared, very recently, a collection of essays devoted to Kantâs political philosophy,
2 some of which are interesting; but even there you will soon see that the question itself is treated as a marginal topic as far as Kant himself was concerned. Of all the books on Kantâs philosophy as a whole, it is only Jaspersâ treatment that devotes at least a quarter of the space to this particular subject. (Jaspers, the only disciple Kant ever had; Saner, the only one Jaspers ever had.) The essays that make up
On History3 or the recent collection called
Kantâs Political Writings4 cannot compare in quality and depth with Kantâs other writings; they certainly do not constitute a âFourth Critique,â as one author called them, eager to claim for them that stature since they happened to be his subject.
5 Kant himself called some of them a mere âplay with ideasâ or a âmere pleasure trip.â
6 And the ironical tone of
Perpetual Peace, by far the most important of them, shows clearly that Kant himself did not take them too seriously. In a letter to Kiesewetter (October 15, 1795), he calls the treatise âreveriesâ (as though he thought of his early fun with Swedenborg, his
Dreams of a Ghost-Seer, Elucidated by Dreams of Metaphysics [1766]). As far as
The Doctrine of Right (or of Law) is concernedâwhich you will find only in the book edited by Reiss and which, if you read it, you will probably find rather boring
and pedanticâit is difficult not to agree with Schopenhauer, who said about it: âIt is as if it were not the work of this great man, but the product of an ordinary common man [
gewöhnlicher Erdensohn].â The concept of law is of great importance in Kantâs practical philosophy, where man is understood as a legislative being; but if we want to study the philosophy of law in general, we certainly shall not turn to Kant but to Pufendorff or Grotius or Montesquieu.
Finally, if you look at the other essaysâeither in the Reiss book or in the other collection (
On History), you will see that many of them are concerned with history, so that, at first, it looks almost as though Kant, like so many after him, had substituted a philosophy of history for a political philosophy; but then, Kantâs concept of history, though quite important in its own right, is not central to his philosophy, and we would turn to Vico or Hegel and Marx if we wanted to inquire into history. In Kant, history is part of nature; the historical subject is the human species understood as part of the creation, though as its final end and creationâs crown, so to speak. What matters in history, whose haphazard, contingent melancholy he never forgot, are not the stories, not the historical individuals, nothing that men did of good or evil, but the secret ruse of nature that caused the species to progress and develop all of its potentialities in the succession of generations. The lifespan of man as an individual is too short to develop all human qualities and possibilities; the history of the species is therefore the process in which âall the seeds planted in it by Nature can fully develop and in which the destiny of the race can be fulfilled here on earth.â
7 This is âworld history,â seen in analogy to the organic development of the individualâchildhood, adolescence, maturity. Kant is never interested in the past; what interests him is the future of the species. Man is driven from Paradise not because of sin and not by an avenging God but by nature, which releases him from her womb and then drives him from the Garden, the âsafe and harmless state of childhood.â
8 That is the beginning of history; its process is progress, and the product of this process is sometimes called culture,
9 sometimes freedom (âfrom the tutelage of nature to the state of freedomâ);
10 and only once, almost in passing, in a parenthesis, does Kant state that it is a question of bringing about âthe highest end intended for man, namely, sociability [
Geselligkeit].â
11(We shall see later the importance of sociability.) Progress itself, the dominant concept of the eighteenth century, is for Kant a
rather melancholy notion; he repeatedly stresses its obviously sad implication for the life of the individual.
If we accept the moral-physical condition of man here in life even on the best terms, that is to say, of a perpetual progression and advance to the highest good which is marked out as his destination, he still cannot . . . unite contentment with the prospect of his condition . . . enduring in an eternal state of change. For the condition in which man now exists remains ever an evil, in comparison to the better condition into which he stands ready to proceed; and the notion of an infinite progression to the ultimate purpose is still simultaneously one prospect in an unending series of evils which . . . do not permit contentment to prevail.
12 Another way of raising objections to my choice of topic, a somewhat indelicate but by no means entirely unjustified way, is to point out that all of the essays that are usually chosenâand that I too have chosenâdate from Kantâs last years and that the decrease of his mental faculties, which finally led into senile imbecility, is a matter of fact. To counteract this argument, I have asked you to read the very early
Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime.
13 To anticipate my own opinion on this matter, which I hope to justify to you in the course of this term: if one knows Kantâs work and takes its biographical circumstances into account, it is rather tempting to turn the argument around and to say that Kant became aware of the political
as distinguished from the social, as part and parcel of manâs condition in the world, rather late in life, when he no longer had either the strength or the time to work out his own philosophy on this particular matter. By this I do not mean to say that Kant, because of the shortness of his life, failed to write the âfourth Critiqueâ but rather that the third Critique, the
Critique of Judgmentâwhich in distinction from the
Critique of Practical Reason was written spontaneously and not, like the
Critique of Practical Reason, in answer to critical observations, questions, and provocationsâactually should have become the book that otherwise is missing in Kantâs great work.
After he had finished the critical business, there were, from his own viewpoint, two questions left, questions that had bothered him all his life and that he had interrupted work on in order first to clear up what he called the âscandal of reasonâ: the fact that âreason contradicts itselfâ
14 or that
thinking transcends the limitations of what we can
know and then gets caught in its
own antinomies. We know from Kantâs own testimony that the turning point in his life was his discovery (in 1770) of the human mindâs cognitive faculties and their limitations, a discovery that took him more than ten years to elaborate and to publish as the
Critique of Pure Reason. We also know from his letters what this immense labor of so many years signified for his other plans and ideas. He writes, of this âmain subject,â that it kept back and obstructed like âa damâ all the other matters he had hoped to finish and publish; that it was like âa stone on his way,â on which he could proceed only after its removal.
15 And when he returned to his concerns of the precritical period, they had, of course, changed somewhat in the light of what he now knew; but they had not changed beyond recognition, nor could we say that they had lost their urgency for him.
The most important change can be indicated in the following way. Prior to the event of 1770, he had intended to write, and soon publish, the
Metaphysics of Morals, a work that in fact he wrote and published only thirty years later. But, at this early date, the book was announced under the title Critique of Moral Taste.
16 When Kant finally turned to the third
Critique, he still called it, to begin with, the Critique of Taste. Thus two things happened: behind taste, a favorite topic of the whole eighteenth century, Kant had discovered an entirely new human faculty, namely, judgment; but, at the same time, he withdrew moral propositions from the competence of this new faculty. In other words: it is now more than taste that will decide about the beautiful and the ugly; but the question of right and wrong is to be decided by neither taste nor judgment but by reason alone.
Second Session
IN THE FIRST LECTURE I said that for Kant, toward the end of his life, two questions were left. The first of these could be summed up, or rather indicated, by the âsociabilityâ of man, that is, the fact that no man can live alone, that men are interdependent not merely in their needs and cares but in their highest faculty, the human min...