Meaning and Metaphysical Necessity
eBook - ePub

Meaning and Metaphysical Necessity

Tristan GrĂžtvedt Haze

Partager le livre
  1. 240 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (adapté aux mobiles)
  4. Disponible sur iOS et Android
eBook - ePub

Meaning and Metaphysical Necessity

Tristan GrĂžtvedt Haze

DĂ©tails du livre
Aperçu du livre
Table des matiĂšres
Citations

À propos de ce livre

This book is about the idea that some true statements would have been true no matter how the world had turned out, while others could have been false. It develops and defends a version of the idea that we tell the difference between these two types of truths in part by reflecting on the meanings of words.

It has often been thought that modal issues—issues about possibility and necessity—are related to issues about meaning. In this book, the author defends the view that the analysis of meaning is not just a preliminary to answering modal questions in philosophy; it is not merely that before we can find out whether something is possible, we need to get clear on what we are talking about. Rather, clarity about meaning often brings with it answers to modal questions. In service of this view, the author analyzes the notion of necessity and develops ideas about linguistic meaning, applying them to several puzzles and problems in philosophy of language.

Meaning and Metaphysical Necessity will be of interest to scholars and advanced students working in metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophical logic.

Foire aux questions

Comment puis-je résilier mon abonnement ?
Il vous suffit de vous rendre dans la section compte dans paramĂštres et de cliquer sur « RĂ©silier l’abonnement ». C’est aussi simple que cela ! Une fois que vous aurez rĂ©siliĂ© votre abonnement, il restera actif pour le reste de la pĂ©riode pour laquelle vous avez payĂ©. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Puis-je / comment puis-je télécharger des livres ?
Pour le moment, tous nos livres en format ePub adaptĂ©s aux mobiles peuvent ĂȘtre tĂ©lĂ©chargĂ©s via l’application. La plupart de nos PDF sont Ă©galement disponibles en tĂ©lĂ©chargement et les autres seront tĂ©lĂ©chargeables trĂšs prochainement. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Quelle est la différence entre les formules tarifaires ?
Les deux abonnements vous donnent un accĂšs complet Ă  la bibliothĂšque et Ă  toutes les fonctionnalitĂ©s de Perlego. Les seules diffĂ©rences sont les tarifs ainsi que la pĂ©riode d’abonnement : avec l’abonnement annuel, vous Ă©conomiserez environ 30 % par rapport Ă  12 mois d’abonnement mensuel.
Qu’est-ce que Perlego ?
Nous sommes un service d’abonnement Ă  des ouvrages universitaires en ligne, oĂč vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  toute une bibliothĂšque pour un prix infĂ©rieur Ă  celui d’un seul livre par mois. Avec plus d’un million de livres sur plus de 1 000 sujets, nous avons ce qu’il vous faut ! DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Prenez-vous en charge la synthÚse vocale ?
Recherchez le symbole Écouter sur votre prochain livre pour voir si vous pouvez l’écouter. L’outil Écouter lit le texte Ă  haute voix pour vous, en surlignant le passage qui est en cours de lecture. Vous pouvez le mettre sur pause, l’accĂ©lĂ©rer ou le ralentir. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Est-ce que Meaning and Metaphysical Necessity est un PDF/ePUB en ligne ?
Oui, vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  Meaning and Metaphysical Necessity par Tristan GrĂžtvedt Haze en format PDF et/ou ePUB ainsi qu’à d’autres livres populaires dans Philosophy et Philosophical Metaphysics. Nous disposons de plus d’un million d’ouvrages Ă  dĂ©couvrir dans notre catalogue.

Informations

Éditeur
Routledge
Année
2022
ISBN
9781000605785
Édition
1

1Groundwork on Necessity

DOI: 10.4324/9781003269700-2

1 The Target Notion

In Naming and Necessity Kripke isolated a notion of necessity which appears to be philosophically central and to admit of cases of the necessary a posteriori; truths which could not have been otherwise, and yet cannot be known without empirical input. This threatens the natural idea that a priori considerations of meaning have a special role to play in answering modal questions in philosophy. In the following chapters I will develop two ways of factorizing the notion of necessity so that there is a clear focal point for a priori considerations. These factorizations will take the form of biconditionals; ‘if and only if’ claims about the conditions under which a statement is necessarily true in the relevant sense. Both factorizations involve a special notion I will introduce for the purpose at hand: the notion of a genuine counterfactual scenario description. While this notion has much of the character of the notion of necessity (or rather, the dual notion of possibility), it differs systematically, and—crucially for our purposes—is arguably a priori tractable. It will then remain to explore the extent to which these a priori considerations may be regarded as semantic, i.e. as considerations about meaning. But first some groundwork is in order. In this chapter I will isolate the target notion of necessity in a bit more detail than in the Introduction, before attempting to dispense with various considerations which may seem to cast doubt on our project before it even gets started.
Kripke introduces the target notion as follows:
We ask whether something might have been true, or might have been false. Well, if something is false, it’s obviously not necessarily true. If it is true, might it have been otherwise? Is it possible that, in this respect, the world should have been different from the way it is? If the answer is ‘no’, then this fact about the world is a necessary one. If the answer is ‘yes’, then this fact about the world is a contingent one.1
Note that Kripke moves freely here between ‘facts about the world’ and things which can be called true or false. In the first instance at least, our concern will be with the notion of necessity as it applies to things which can be called true or false: statements, or propositions.2 To register this terminologically, we might say that our topic is necessity de dicto. Another term we may use to further pin down our topic is ‘subjunctive’ (in contrast to ‘indicative’): Kripke’s characterization cashes out necessity in terms of counterfactual scenarios—scenarios considered as counterfactual, rather than scenarios considered as actual.3 That is, our topic has to do with what could have been the case, rather than what could actually be the case. This could also be emphasized by calling our topic ‘counterfactual necessity’, but ‘subjunctive’ is better established in the literature.4
For brevity I will tend to drop the qualifications ‘subjunctive’ and ‘de dicto’. In the literature, our topic is most often called ‘metaphysical necessity’, and this is in keeping with Kripke’s classification of the notion as metaphysical as opposed to epistemological. I will avoid this loaded label for the time being, but in Chapter 7 I will begin to interrogate it.
A further important point to note is that the target notion is supposed to be the dual of an unrestricted notion of possibility.5 Consider: ‘It is true that I stayed home yesterday. This couldn’t have been otherwise, as I had to be there to let the electrician in’. This utterance may be true, but in that case we are dealing with a restricted range of ways things could have been. We are ignoring ways things could have been in which I never made the appointment with the electrician, or the appointment was on a different day, or I stop caring about electricity. This supplement to Kripke’s characterization has become customary. Witness Timothy Williamson in an interview:
Something is metaphysically necessary if it couldn’t have been otherwise, in the most unrestricted sense.6
Or Daniel Stoljar, referring to:
(
) the completely unrestricted sense of possibility that philosophers sometimes call ‘logical’7 or ‘metaphysical’ possibility (
).8
Or this stipulation made by van Inwagen:
Modal terms will be used in their ‘metaphysical’ or ‘unrestricted’ sense (
).9
It will also help to consider some examples to which the target notion applies—particularly cases lying outside the overlap of necessity and apriority. As we saw in the Introduction, perhaps the clearest example of a necessary a posteriori statement is an identity statement involving proper names (conditionalized on existence in order to get around the worry that the object in question might not have existed, in which case it would not have been identical to anything). If a statement of the form ‘If a exists, then a = b’ is true, it is necessarily true, but it may not be knowable a priori. Regarding the contingent a priori, perhaps the most straightforward type of case is when a name is stipulated to refer to whatever object satisfies some definite description whose denotation is a contingent matter. For instance, if I stipulate10 that ‘Julius’ is to pick out the actual inventor of the zip (if there is one), then the statement ‘If Julius exists, Julius invented the zip’ is a priori: in virtue of the way I have set ‘Julius’ up to work, it just can’t turn out empirically that Julius exists and yet didn’t invent the zip after all. Still, the statement is contingent:11 someone else could have invented the zip.12
This trafficking in examples brings up a methodological point: this approach to factorizing necessity is set up to be able to accommodate necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori statements, and in developing it I have treated what seem to me the most convincing examples as data. When illustrating the approach, I take the orthodox Kripkean line on a few examples. However, I intend the approach to be quite flexible, offering plenty of room for disagreement about them.
Another important point is that the target notion might be vague, in the sense of there being unclear or borderline cases. (It seems pretty clear that ‘Saul Kripke is not a number’ is necessarily true, whereas ‘Saul Kripke is an influential philosopher’ is contingently true. But with some truths, such as ‘Saul Kripke is male’, or ‘Saul Kripke was born in the twentieth century’, things are not so clear.) It is important to allow for this explicitly, since the appearance of unclear or borderline cases may seem to cast doubt on the legitimacy of the notion. Indeed, it might seem like this is the type of notion which can’t really be vague if it is to be legitimate; but this I think stems from attaching dubious epistemic hopes to the notion, as I explain in Chapters 7 and 8.
One final introductory point: while for simplicity’s sake I proceed for now as though there is a single target notion, I do not really mean to rule out the view that there is more than one notion which fits Kripke’s characterization and key examples.13 On the contrary, I end up taking this prospect seriously in Chapters 7 and 8.
So much for introducing the target notion. The next part of the necessary groundwork takes the form of ground-clearing; I want to deal in advance with some considerations which might seem to cast doubt upon our project of attempting to rescue the idea that there is something a priori and semantic about necessity.

2 Why Not Stick to Indicative Necessity?

Kripke distinguished metaphysical or subjunctive necessity from apriority, and argued that there are a posteriori truths which are metaphysically or subjunctively necessary. This has led philosophers to doubt whether a priori reflection, in particular reflection on the meanings of expressions, has a special role to play with respect to modal issues. In this book I am trying to address such doubts. But what if the most philosophically central modality is the indicative one that Kripke put aside in order to focus on the subjunctive? That is, what if the most philosophically central modal considerations are about what could actually be the case, rather than what could have been the case? If that were so, the project of this book would be ill-motivated.
This challenge must be given its due. One reply to it that I emphatically do not endorse is to object that indicative necessity is merely epistemic, whereas subjunctive modality is objective (‘metaphysical’). Firstly, such an objection may be countered with a ‘So what?’;14 a notion being epistemic hardly disqualifies it from being philosophically central. Furthermore, if it is epistemic, the notion is epistemic only in a general, idealized way; it is not about what is knowable for some particular person or group, or even humanity in general. If indicative necessity is epistemic, then it just is apriority or something closely related, and a priori truths are those which can in principle be known without recourse to experience. An even bigger problem with the objection is that indicative necessity may not be merely epistemic at all. The indicatively necessarily true statements, it might be argued, are those which are inherently incapable of being false. Given what they mean, the only truth value they can have is true.15 Knowability without recourse to experience lies downstream from that. Apriority is a consequence of indicative necessity. The fact that a statement is only capable of truth is an objective fact about that statement, not itself having to do with how it may be known.
This viewpoint about indicative necessity and its explaining typical cases of apriority is controversial and hard to maintain given the state of present philosophical thinking about linguistic meaning, but the views I develop in Chapters 4 and 5 fit well with it. I want to remain open to the idea that with modal issues in philosophy, the relevant modality is often indicative or might as well be. It is nonetheless important that we clarify subjunctive modality and its relation to meaning. If a modal issue arising in philosophy can be construed as subjunctive, then it often will be, and so we need to understand the place of a priori reflection, and reflection on meaning in particular, with respect to the issue so framed. One reason that modal issues tend to get framed subjunctively is that indicative necessity—as opposed to the apriority that stems from it—is currently poorly understood, indeed hardly recognized as a distinctive objective modality. There are also powerful imaginative considerations in favour of the subjunctive. The characteristic way in which subjunctive possibility and impossibility judgements depend on empirical input encourages the view that subjunctive modality is as it were better informed than indicative. There are the ways the world could actually be—the ways depicted by the world of coherent representations, so to speak—but then there is the more circumscribed range of ways the world really could have been, and our knowledge of this space must be empirically informed. This fits almost uncannily well with general ideas about how philosophy ought properly ...

Table des matiĂšres