Economics, Philosophy and Physics
eBook - ePub

Economics, Philosophy and Physics

Ching-Yao Hsieh, Meng-Hua Ye

Condividi libro
  1. 208 pagine
  2. English
  3. ePUB (disponibile sull'app)
  4. Disponibile su iOS e Android
eBook - ePub

Economics, Philosophy and Physics

Ching-Yao Hsieh, Meng-Hua Ye

Dettagli del libro
Anteprima del libro
Indice dei contenuti
Citazioni

Informazioni sul libro

This book traces the relationship between ideas and methodological perspectives in economics to the fields of philosophy and the physical sciences. It is aimed at students of economics who want to learn about the philosophical underpinnings and scientific foundations of contemporary economic theory. The authors show how advances in scientific knowledge have had an impact on philosophy that in turn influenced the development of economic thought.

Domande frequenti

Come faccio ad annullare l'abbonamento?
È semplicissimo: basta accedere alla sezione Account nelle Impostazioni e cliccare su "Annulla abbonamento". Dopo la cancellazione, l'abbonamento rimarrà attivo per il periodo rimanente già pagato. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
È possibile scaricare libri? Se sì, come?
Al momento è possibile scaricare tramite l'app tutti i nostri libri ePub mobile-friendly. Anche la maggior parte dei nostri PDF è scaricabile e stiamo lavorando per rendere disponibile quanto prima il download di tutti gli altri file. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
Che differenza c'è tra i piani?
Entrambi i piani ti danno accesso illimitato alla libreria e a tutte le funzionalità di Perlego. Le uniche differenze sono il prezzo e il periodo di abbonamento: con il piano annuale risparmierai circa il 30% rispetto a 12 rate con quello mensile.
Cos'è Perlego?
Perlego è un servizio di abbonamento a testi accademici, che ti permette di accedere a un'intera libreria online a un prezzo inferiore rispetto a quello che pagheresti per acquistare un singolo libro al mese. Con oltre 1 milione di testi suddivisi in più di 1.000 categorie, troverai sicuramente ciò che fa per te! Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Perlego supporta la sintesi vocale?
Cerca l'icona Sintesi vocale nel prossimo libro che leggerai per verificare se è possibile riprodurre l'audio. Questo strumento permette di leggere il testo a voce alta, evidenziandolo man mano che la lettura procede. Puoi aumentare o diminuire la velocità della sintesi vocale, oppure sospendere la riproduzione. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Economics, Philosophy and Physics è disponibile online in formato PDF/ePub?
Sì, puoi accedere a Economics, Philosophy and Physics di Ching-Yao Hsieh, Meng-Hua Ye in formato PDF e/o ePub, così come ad altri libri molto apprezzati nelle sezioni relative a Business e Business General. Scopri oltre 1 milione di libri disponibili nel nostro catalogo.

Informazioni

Editore
Routledge
Anno
2016
ISBN
9781315489230
Edizione
1
Argomento
Business

Chapter 1

Newtonian Physics, Philosophy, and Economics

The medieval world view was severely damaged by two revolutions: the Copernican Revolution in astronomy (1543) and the Cartesian Revolution in philosophy (1637). "The pernican Revolution," as pointed out by Thomas S. Kuhn, "was a revolution in ideas, a transformation in man’s conception of the universe and of his own relation to it. Again and again this history of Renaissance thought has been proclaimed an epochal turning point in the intellectual development of Western man."1 In other words, the Copernican Revolution paved the way for the conception of the mechanical world view.
There had been two strands of thought in the quest for new certainty before Newton. In his Novum Organum (1620), Francis Bacon (1561–1626) launched a skillful attack on scholasticism and urged philosophers to adopt the empirical method. The other strand was Réné Descartes’s (1596–1650) rationalist quest for certain knowledge. In Discourse upon Method (1637), Descartes started with radical doubt of everything and ended with a firm belief in the view that nature was a perfect machine governed by exact mathematical laws (Descartes’s "universal mathematics"). Thus, a new order of the universe was established and a new language had to be developed for the description of this new order. Descartes invented analytical geometry (the Cartesian coordinates) for this purpose. David Bohm observes:
To use coordinates is in effect to order our perception and our thinking . . . . [O]nce men were ready to conceive of the universe as a machine, they would naturally tend to take the order of coordinates as a universally relevant one, valid for all basic descriptions in physics.2
This idea is depicted by Figure 1.1: in order to specify the position of a particle it is necessary to know three distances (space has three dimensions), namely (a) length, represented by the Cartesian axis X in Figure 1.1, (b) breadth, represented by Cartesian axis Y, and (c) height, represented by the Cartesian axis Z. The three distances, X, Y, and Z, are called Cartesian coordinates. The position of the particle G is expressed in the form of (X, Y, Z). The use of the Cartesian coordinates was implicit in Newtonian physics. The introduction of the Cartesian coordinates was indeed an important contribution of the Cartesian Revolution.
Another salient feature of the Cartesian Revolution, which is relevant to the subsequent development of economic analysis, was the so-called “reductionist methodology.” According to Descartes, certain knowledge should be achieved through intuition and deduction. This methodology is succinctly summarized by Fritjof Capra:
Descartes’ method is analytic. It consists of breaking up thoughts and problems into pieces and in arranging these in their logical order. This analytic method of reasoning is probably Descartes’ greatest contribution to science. It has become an essential characteristic of modem scientific thought and has proved extremely useful in the development of scientific theories and the realization of complex technological projects.3
A third feature of Cartesian philosophy was the so-called “mind-matter duality.” According to Descartes, there are two independent and separate realms of nature. One of the realms is the realm of mind; he referred to this as “res cognitas.” The other realm is the realm of matter, which he called “res extensa.” This Cartesian duality led to two tenets of Western sciences: (a) the observer of the physical universe only observes but never disturbs; and (b) the physical universe is a machine governed by exact mathematical laws.
Figure 1.1. The use of Cartesian coordinates to fix the position of a particle in space
Figure 1.1. The use of Cartesian coordinates to fix the position of a particle in space
In the realm of natural sciences, the Copemican heliocentric astronomy was subsequently refined by Johann Kepler (1571–1630). Among other things, Kepler emphasized that the path of each planet is not circular as depicted by Copernicus, but rather is an ellipse with the sun slightly off center at a point known as the focus of the ellipse.
The most famous contemporary of Kepler was Galileo Galilei (1564–1642). It is interesting to note that William Shakespeare was born in the same year as Galileo and that Isaac Newton was born in the year he died. It was Galileo who finally broke the lingering bondage of Aristotelian physics and medieval scholasticism. Thus, Galileo, more than any other single person, was responsible for the birth of modern science.
Galileo’s devotion to obtain quantitative description of nature may be best illustrated by his law of falling bodies: d = 1/2gt2, where d denotes the number of feet the body falls; g stands for the constant acceleration of a body dropped in a vacuum (g = 32 feet per second); and t is time in seconds. Thus, the law may be rewritten as d = 16t2.
Galileo did not offer explainations for why phenomena occur, such as Heron’s famous explanation that “nature abhors a vacuum.” His formula is precise and quantitatively complete in a way that is characteristic of modern science.
It may be said that it was Galileo who planted the seed of what John Hicks called the “New Causality”:
Causality can only be asserted, i n terms of New Causality, if we have some theory, or generalization, into which observed events can be fitted; to suppose that we have theories into which all events can be fitted, is to make a large claim indeed.4
Frangois Quesnay’s tableau economique (1758), the quantity theory of money elucidated by John Locke (1632–1704), David Hume (1711–76), and Richard Cantillon (1680–1734), as well as David Ricardo’s one-sector “corn model” (1815) brought forth during the so-called “corn laws controversy” were all in line with the “New Causality.” Even today economists are still attempting to fit observed events into some mathematical models.

Newton’s Grand Synthesis

The climax of the intellectual revolution in phi...

Indice dei contenuti