Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution I
eBook - ePub

Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution I

Hal Draper

  1. 272 pagine
  2. English
  3. ePUB (disponibile sull'app)
  4. Disponibile su iOS e Android
eBook - ePub

Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution I

Hal Draper

Dettagli del libro
Anteprima del libro
Indice dei contenuti
Citazioni

Informazioni sul libro

Volume I of Hal Draper’s definitive and masterful study of Marx’s political thought, which focuses on Marx’s attitude toward democracy, the state, intellectuals as revolutionaries, and much, much more.

This series, Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution, represents an exhaustive and definitive treatment of Marx’s political theory, policy, and practice. Marx and Engels paid continuing attention to a host of problems of revolution, in addition to constructing their “grand theory.” All these political and social analyses are brought together in these volumes, as the author draws not only on the original writings of Marx and Engels but also on the sources that they used in formulating their ideas and the many commentaries on their published work.

Draper’s series is a massive and immensely valuable scholarly undertaking. The bibliography alone will stand as a rich resource for years to come. Yet despite the scholarly treatment, the writing is direct, forceful, and unpedantic throughout, and will appeal to the beginning student as much as the advanced reader.

Domande frequenti

Come faccio ad annullare l'abbonamento?
È semplicissimo: basta accedere alla sezione Account nelle Impostazioni e cliccare su "Annulla abbonamento". Dopo la cancellazione, l'abbonamento rimarrà attivo per il periodo rimanente già pagato. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
È possibile scaricare libri? Se sì, come?
Al momento è possibile scaricare tramite l'app tutti i nostri libri ePub mobile-friendly. Anche la maggior parte dei nostri PDF è scaricabile e stiamo lavorando per rendere disponibile quanto prima il download di tutti gli altri file. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
Che differenza c'è tra i piani?
Entrambi i piani ti danno accesso illimitato alla libreria e a tutte le funzionalità di Perlego. Le uniche differenze sono il prezzo e il periodo di abbonamento: con il piano annuale risparmierai circa il 30% rispetto a 12 rate con quello mensile.
Cos'è Perlego?
Perlego è un servizio di abbonamento a testi accademici, che ti permette di accedere a un'intera libreria online a un prezzo inferiore rispetto a quello che pagheresti per acquistare un singolo libro al mese. Con oltre 1 milione di testi suddivisi in più di 1.000 categorie, troverai sicuramente ciò che fa per te! Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Perlego supporta la sintesi vocale?
Cerca l'icona Sintesi vocale nel prossimo libro che leggerai per verificare se è possibile riprodurre l'audio. Questo strumento permette di leggere il testo a voce alta, evidenziandolo man mano che la lettura procede. Puoi aumentare o diminuire la velocità della sintesi vocale, oppure sospendere la riproduzione. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution I è disponibile online in formato PDF/ePub?
Sì, puoi accedere a Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution I di Hal Draper in formato PDF e/o ePub, così come ad altri libri molto apprezzati nelle sezioni relative a Politica e relazioni internazionali e Comunismo, post-comunismo e socialismo. Scopri oltre 1 milione di libri disponibili nel nostro catalogo.
I THE POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT OF THE YOUNG MARX

1 THE DEMOCRATIC EXTREMIST

Marx entered active political life at the age of twenty-four as a liberal democratic journalist, the champion of political democracy. This period opens at the beginning of 1842, when he wrote his first published political article, and closes toward the latter part of the following year, when he became a communist. The development in between, which transformed him from a radical-democratic liberal into a revolutionary-democratic communist, is centered around his work for the Rheinische Zeitung (RZ) of Cologne, of which he became the editor in October 1842.
At the beginning of this period Marx’s main interest lay in and around the field of philosophy; by its end he had reoriented toward social and political issues. That is, he began it as a radical philosopher and ended it as a social revolutionary.
The transition was not primarily a philosophical process, nor one made through philosophical lucubrations. This young Marx is often portrayed as having come to a revolutionary understanding of society through a critique of Hegel’s texts on the state and society. The biographical fact, however, is that he came to the content of his critique of the Hegelian view of the state through a year and a half of rubbing his nose against the social and political facts of life, which he encountered as the crusading editor of the most extreme leftist democratic newspaper in pre-1848 Germany, as well as in reading contemporary political literature.

1. STATE AND CIVIL SOCIETY IN HEGELESE

During this RZ period and for some time after, Marx shared a stock of conceptions about the state with the Young Hegelian milieu in which he had matured, within a framework of ideas that remained basically Hegelian even while departing from Hegel in important conclusions. For our purposes it is especially vital to understand the Hegelian distinction between state and civil society, a way of thinking we will encounter often in the next few chapters.
The difficulty for the modern reader is not simply terminological, a matter of learning the Hegelian tag for phenomena which go by some other label in plain English or German. One reason Hegelian terminology remains puzzling even after a formal explanation is that it reflects a different way of ordering social phenomena in one’s mind; it dissects social reality along different lines.
To begin with: the “rational” state, involving a just and ethical relationship of harmony among the elements of society, is an ideal against which existing states are to be measured. The extent to which it “really” is a state depends on its closeness to the ideal.1 The essence of the state is eternal, not historical. For Hegel, its aim is the “realization of rational freedom”; as “an association of free men mutually educating each other,” it is the “great organism in which juridical, ethical, and political freedom has to achieve realization.” (These phrases are, as a matter of fact, from an article by Marx in the RZ.)2 The frame of reference, then, is not necessarily anything that actually exists, but rather what should exist.
Next, the word state does not refer merely to the political institutions of society, but to all of public affairs and life in a certain broad sense. It embraces the totality or collectivity of humanity’s communal concerns; it is the institutionalization of communality in society, not of political organization in our narrower sense. The “political state” is only one aspect of this.
If the state is the communal sphere of society, in contrast civil society (bürgerliche Gesellschaft) embraces the private world of individual strivings and interests. Hence it especially comprises the economic strivings of individuals. In modern times, bourgeois economic activity, with its emphasis on privatized dog-eat-dog relations, is preeminently in the realm of civil society.*
But the term becomes ambiguous as its meaning shifts from the civil society of the old regime to the civil society of modern times; the medieval Bürger becomes the modern bourgeois. In German, bürgerliche Gesellschaft can mean either “civil society” or “bourgeois society,” depending on its context and the user’s intention. When the context is modern times, and therefore the bourgeois society of modern times, it inevitably tends to connote bourgeois society even when it is properly translated “civil society.” The term operates on a sliding scale of meaning. In translations a conscious choice must be made, but the German usage did not necessarily involve a consciousness of the alternatives.
This caution is interestingly confirmed by the fact that Marx first showed awareness of the slipperiness of the term in The German Ideology, the work in which he first thoroughly emancipated himself from the Hegelian framework in social thought. Here he uses bürgerliche Gesellschaft explicitly to mean the economic sphere of society, which determines the state as its political superstructure: “It embraces the whole commercial and industrial life of a given [historical] stage. …” He now sees the ambiguity of the term from outside Hegelianism, and feels called on to explain:
The term bürgerliche Gesellschaft emerged in the eighteenth century, when property relationships had already extricated themselves from the ancient and medieval communal society. Bürgerliche Gesellschaft as such only develops with the bourgeoisie; the social organization evolving directly out of production and commerce, which in all ages forms the basis of the state and of the rest of the ideological superstructure, has however always been designated by the same name.6**
In full maturity, in one of his most important summary statements, Marx traced his developed theory of the state back to his first critique of Hegel’s conception of state and civil society:
My investigation led to the result that legal relations as well as forms of the state are to be grasped neither from themselves nor from the so-called general development of the human mind, but rather have their roots in the material conditions of life, the sum total of which Hegel, following the example of the Englishmen and Frenchmen of the eighteenth century, combines under the name of “civil society”; that, however, the anatomy of civil society is to be sought in political economy.8
That is: Marx’s investigation led him to believe that Hegel’s views on the relation between state and civil society had to be changed. Nevertheless, it is useful to remember that his central starting point was the problem so posed.
The broad use of state in Hegelese presents translation problems. Marx’s early formulations, in the Hegelian spirit, often come close to counterposing the state concept (the ideal state) against what we would now understand by the term. What we would call the state he might label the political state or the Beamtenstaat—the bureaucracy’s state apparatus, or just the bureaucracy. Thus, in one article Marx wrote that the “bureaucracy is still too powerful, that not so much the whole state as part of the state, the ‘government,’ carries on a real political life [Staatsleben].”9 In the present chapter, Staat in one context is translated the “body politic,” in the hope of suggesting a wider sphere of public affairs than is presently connoted by state. In another context Staatgeist is translated “public spirit,” for today “state spirit” would suggest almost the very opposite of what Marx was trying to say in 1842.

2. THE WINDS OF FREEDOM

The arena of Marx’s political debut was the Rhineland, which differed from the rest of Germany in significant respects.
1. When Marx was born his native Rhineland was only three years away from having been part of revolutionary France. In 1795 it had been taken over by Napoleon’s armies and socially remolded. Only in 1815 was it annexed by Prussia: annexed, but far from completely Prussianized even by the 1840s. Even the legal system remained gallicized. As Heine put it, the Rhinelander was thus made into “a Prussian by the power of conquest.” Engels echoed this in the midst of revolution in Cologne in 1849: “It was only by force that we [Rhinelanders] became subjects to Prussia and remained so. We were never Prussians.” He adds: “But now, when we are marched against Hungary, when Prussian territory is trodden by Russian robber bands—now we feel like Prussians, yes indeed, we feel what a disgrace it is to bear the name of Prussian!10
2. The Rhineland was the most industrialized and economically developed section of Germany, with the most conscious liberal bourgeoisie. Top leaders of the 1848 revolutionary government were going to be Rhenish—indeed, were to be men who had been sponsors of the Rheinische Zeitung.* The Prussian bureaucratic system, wrote a modern historian, “harmonized but poorly with the free industrial communities of the Rhenish provinces, where Prussian bureaucrats were perpetually at daggers’ points with the native population.”13 Further, the peasantry of the Rhineland was advanced and modern as compared with that of Prussia.14
3. In consequence of these facts, the intellectual and social climate of the region retained some of the heat generated by the revolutionary furor on the other side of the Rhine. “French” ideas—constitutionalism, representative democracy, Liberty-Equality-Fraternity, etc.—were not so foreign.
Have we forgotten [wrote Engels in 1888] that the whole left bank of the Rhine … was pro-French-minded when the Germans moved into it again in 1814, and remained pro-French-minded till 1848 when the revolution rehabilitated the Germans in the Rhinelanders’ eyes? that Heine’s pro-French enthusiasm and even his Bonapartism were nothing but the echo of general public feeling west of the Rhine?15
Even French socialist ideas had penetrated, especially in the form most appealing to a modernizing, industrializing new class: Saint-Simonism. These new notions were denounced from the pulpit by the archbishop in Trier, Marx’s birthplace; Marx’s future father-in-law talked them up at home; and his law professor did the same at the University of Berlin.16 The first German socialist propagandist, Ludwig Gall, had recently used Trier as his center of operation. Marx’s mind, long before it turned to social issues, was formed on the front where French ideas met German cultural patterns.
The winds from France, and the breezes wafted up from the Rhenish liberal bourgeoisie, bore the word liberté/Freiheit to the ears of those interested in widening political participation in decision-making by the people. A specific freedom was the occasion for Marx’s debut as a political activist.
The new king, Friedrich Wilhelm IV, whose accession to the throne in 1840 had been eagerly awaited by the liberals, had made noises about broadening the freedom of the press, and in December 1841 he promulgated new regulations (“instructions”) on the censorship. Liberals and even Young Hegelians hailed the step enthusiastically; indeed, so did the Rheinische Zeitung at first.17 In two articles Marx set out to dissect the pseudoliberalism of the new regulations and counterpose his own conception of freedom—that is, political democracy.
We must stress that under the existing circumstances the issue of free press and censorship was not just one of many liberal issues. The liberal democrats considered it, along with the constitution, the key to political change.18

3. THE “FREEDOM OF THE PRESS” ARTICLES

We shall consider Marx’s two articles together. One, “Comments on the Latest Prussian Censorship Instructions,” was the first article he ever wrote, but although it was written in January 1842, it was not published till the following year, in Switzerland. The other, dealing with the debates on freedom of the press in the Rhenish Diet, was his first article to see print, in the RZ.
The RZ article first takes up the speakers who opposed freedom of the press, analyzing the arguments used by deputies of three of the social estates (Stände)* represented in the Diet: the princes, the landed gentry, and the “cities” (the urban bourgeoisie). It then discusses the arguments used by supporters of freedom of the press, from the cities and from the fourth estate (the peasantry).
At this point Marx is writing within the framework of a bourgeois-democratic view of society, in the sense that he does not question private property in production, especially in land. Similarly, his operative social theory is that of his intellectual milieu: to defend freedom, he writes, “I must grasp it in its essential character, not in external relations”19—a characteristically idealist formulation. But the important thing about these first two articles is how far he goes in a direction which is incompatible with the framework, and becomes ready to burst through it. For while theory (“philosophy”) tells him he must grasp the subject in some way other than “in external relations,” it is preci...

Indice dei contenuti

Stili delle citazioni per Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution I

APA 6 Citation

Draper, H. (1977). Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution I ([edition unavailable]). Monthly Review Press. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/721094/karl-marxs-theory-of-revolution-i-pdf (Original work published 1977)

Chicago Citation

Draper, Hal. (1977) 1977. Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution I. [Edition unavailable]. Monthly Review Press. https://www.perlego.com/book/721094/karl-marxs-theory-of-revolution-i-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Draper, H. (1977) Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution I. [edition unavailable]. Monthly Review Press. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/721094/karl-marxs-theory-of-revolution-i-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Draper, Hal. Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution I. [edition unavailable]. Monthly Review Press, 1977. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.