This Is Bioethics
eBook - ePub

This Is Bioethics

An Introduction

Ruth F. Chadwick, Udo Schüklenk

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

This Is Bioethics

An Introduction

Ruth F. Chadwick, Udo Schüklenk

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Should editing the human genome be allowed? What are the ethical implications of social restrictions during a pandemic? Is it ethical to use animals in clinical research? Is prioritizing COVID-19 treatment increasing deaths from other causes? Bioethics?is a dynamic field of inquiry that draws on interdisciplinary expertise and methodology to address normative issues in healthcare, medicine, biomedical research, biotechnology, public health, and the environment. This Is Bioethics is an ideal introductory textbook for students new to the field, exploring the fundamental questions, concepts, and issues within this rapidly evolving area of study.

Assuming no prior knowledge of the subject, this accessible volume helps students consider both traditional and cutting-edge questions, develop informed and defensible answers, and evaluate the strengths and weaknesses of a diverse range ofethical positions in medicine. The authors avoid complex technical terms and jargon in favor of an easy-to-follow, informal writing style with engaging chapters designed to stimulate student interest and encourage class discussion. The book also features a deep dive into the realm of global public health ethics, including the response to the COVID-19 pandemic. It considers topics like triage decision-making, the proportionality of society's response to COVID-19, whether doctors have a professional obligation to treat COVID-19 patients, and whether vaccines for this virus should be mandatory.

A timely addition to the acclaimed This Is Philosophy ?series, This Is Bioethics is the ideal primary textbook for undergraduate bioethics and practical ethics courses, and is a must-have reference for students in philosophy, biology, biochemistry, and medicine.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is This Is Bioethics an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access This Is Bioethics by Ruth F. Chadwick, Udo Schüklenk in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Medizin & Ethik in der Medizin. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2020
ISBN
9781118770733
Edition
1
Topic
Medizin

1
INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS

1.1 Imagine you were running a medical non‐governmental organization (NGO) established to preserve the lives of poverty‐stricken people in resource poor countries. Your NGO is also usually among the first to provide emergency assistance in case natural emergencies such as tsunamis strike. However, you did notice that agencies evaluating your efficiency1 give you a below‐average ranking. That is a worry to your fundraising staff, mostly because you rely on donations and such ratings are said to impact eventually negatively, on your capacity to raise cash. You investigate what the problem is, and it turns out that the ratings agency is critical of your policy of responding mostly in cases of high‐impact disasters such as earthquakes, floods or civil wars, because they invariably require a highly resource intensive intervention. The agency’s verdict is that, on the same capital outlay, you could preserve more lives in developing countries if you aimed at establishing medium‐ to long‐term health delivery solutions, including setting up primary health care facilities, beginning vaccination programs, and other such relatively low‐cost means. Chartering private jets to fly emergency teams in response to disaster also preserves lives deserving to be rescued, the ratings agency says, but it demonstrably results in a substantially lower number of lives preserved than you could preserve if you dropped such actions in favor of working toward better health care delivery infrastructure in the countries you usually serve.
1.2 So, if your objective is to preserve lives in developing countries, the ratings agency might be correct in saying that you only preserve a suboptimal number of lives. You could do better. Should you change your policy though? After all, what the ratings agency proposes implies, if you were to act on it, is that those in most dire need, say those living in war‐torn countries with minimal health care infrastructure, should be toward the bottom end of your list of priorities, because assisting such people would cost more – per life preserved – to succeed. All other things being equal, more lives could be preserved if the NGO focused on preserving not those most in need but perhaps those whose lives are also threatened but who could be helped with the deployment of fewer resources. Should we only care about the number of lives preserved then, or do other factors matter, too, such as for instance that some people, possibly due to no fault of their own, live in particularly abysmal conditions? Should we factor in the amount of resources required to nurse such people back to a life that would permit them to live independently? Should the age of the to‐be‐rescued matter? Should it matter whether they have a family dependent on their support? Questions such as these are fundamentally ethical questions. And this chapter is about ethics, it is about right and wrong, good and bad, and how we can go about judging alternative courses of action that might be available to us.
1.3 What are the fundamental purposes of ethics then? Unsurprisingly, one of the purposes of ethics is to offer us clear action guidance when we are faced with a particular ethical problem. Of course, action guidance alone is not sufficient, or else an ethicist telling us what we ought to do is not much different to what a preacher or a taxi driver, engineer or medical doctor could tell us. Anyone can admonish us to do this or do that when faced with an ethically challenging situation. All of us almost certainly would have a view on what the NGO chief should be doing. In fact, most of us would probably happily add our two cents worth of opinion when asked what we think the NGO chief should do, policy wise. Thinking about what she ought to do engages with ethics. That takes us to the second objective of ethics. It is to do with the normative justification for the advice given. The preacher’s advice would derive its authority from the claim that she knows what a higher authority (say a God) wants us to do. Of course, many people today are atheists2 or agnostics3, and many of those who are not atheists hold a large number of different deities dear to their hearts, all with competing action guidance derived from their respective sources of godly wisdom. For all we know, the taxi driver and engineer might just reply that that is how they feel, or possibly even think, about the problem at hand. Let us leave aside, for a moment, that in ancient Greece there were no taxi drivers or engineers as we understand them today. During those times their approach to ethics would have led to them being labeled as Sophists4, that is a group of philosophers who subscribe to the view that there are no objectively right or wrong answers to ethical questions, and that answers to ethical questions are at best reflective of someone’s subjective, strongly held beliefs or feelings. What gave way to the birth of modern ethics were philosophers like Plato5 and his teacher Socrates who both believed that we can actually give right or wrong answers to questions about what is ethically good or bad. We will return to their take on ethics in a moment. How might the medical doctor in our example respond to the ratings agency’s ethical challenge? Trying to do better than the Sophists of the world, she could refer to guidance documents issued, for instance by her national medical association’s ethics people6, or those issued by the World Medical Association7, a worldwide umbrella organization of national medical associations, or possibly the World Health Organization8. But what if these organizations have actually omitted to address the problem at hand in their guidance documents? And, even if they haven’t, quotes from a document don’t constitute an ethical justification. What if the document quoted got it wrong? It turns out, we have good reason to be skeptical about famous historical medical guidance documents such as the Hippocratic Oath9. Robert M. Veatch explains why the Hippocratic Oath isn’t a document medical professionals ought to aspire to. According to Veatch just about everything is wrong about it, from its pledge to questionable Greek deities to a cultish understanding of medicine as a secretive practice to practical guidance that prioritizes individual patient interest always over the greater good of the society (Veatch 2012a, 10–29). To put it in Veatch’s own words, ‘the Oath is so controversial and so offensive that it can no longer stand alongside religious and secular alternatives. […] The Hippocratic Oath is unacceptable to any thinking person. It should offend the patient and challenge the health care professional to look elsewhere for moral authority’ (Veatch 2012a, 1). Veatch tells us, somewhat reassuringly, that the Oath today is used in so many variations in the world’s medical schools that sometimes only fragments of the original document seem to remain (Veatch 2012b).
1.4 Be mindful that even if we agreed with the content of the Hippocratic Oath or a modern version of it, and even if they actually provided us with guidance for the problem under consideration, we would again have to take it on authority that we should go about the NGO’s problem in one particular way and not in another, unless there is an ethical justification provided why we should do what it admonishes us to do. Given that in our scenario almost certainly a lot of people would disagree with whatever it is that is being proposed, policy wise, it is important that we get our justification right. Here is where ethics’ second purpose comes in: In addition to providing us with action guidance, it must also provide us with a reasoned justification for the guidance given.
1.5 As we will discover, there exist a fair amount of competing ethical theories, some more influential than others, that succeed with varying degrees of success both on the action guidance as well as on the action justification fronts. How should we decide then, which one, or which set of them to adopt for our own purposes? Is it ok to use one set of theories for one type of problem and another set of theories for another type of problem? Couldn’t we choose virtue ethics for decision‐making at the hospital bedside, but decide to go with utilitarianism for matters of resource allocation decision‐making? But why should we do that, as opposed to just the opposite? Could there be a meta‐theory telling us which theoretical approach to deploy under what circumstances? Or must we determine which theory is the right one and try to abide by its guidance as best as we can, even if some of that guidance is turning out to be deeply counter‐intuitive? Well, these are questions about the nature of ethics; they ask whether there can be a true ethics, whether ethical statements must be of a particular kind, whether they can be objectively true or false, or whether they ultimately boil down to statements expressing our feelings. These and other questions are typically analyzed by meta‐ethicists. They don’t create ethical theories, rather they create theories about ethics. There are also legitimate questions about the extent to which ethical theories truly lend themselves to be ‘applied’ in some sense or another to problems such as the one mentioned at the beginning of this chapter. We will not engage in this sort of theorizing about ethics in this chapter, with the exception of a few paragraphs on ethical relativism. The reason for this is that the discussions driving meta‐ethics are quite technical in nature, and by and large there is no obviously correct solution to many of its controversies. Even in the absence of final answers to many of these questions, however, it is still quite possible to undertake ethical analyses. As we will see throughout this book, some arguments are more plausible than others; certain types of argument, such as for instance slippery‐slope based arguments, are almost always flawed, and so on and so forth. However, you can easily read up on meta‐ethical theories elsewhere. (McMillan 2018) A wonderful source o...

Table of contents