Speculation, Trading, and Bubbles
eBook - ePub

Speculation, Trading, and Bubbles

José Scheinkman, Kenneth Arrow, Patrick Bolton, Joseph E. Stiglitz, Sanford Grossman

Share book
  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Speculation, Trading, and Bubbles

José Scheinkman, Kenneth Arrow, Patrick Bolton, Joseph E. Stiglitz, Sanford Grossman

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

As long as there have been financial markets, there have been bubbles—those moments in which asset prices inflate far beyond their intrinsic value, often with ruinous results. Yet economists are slow to agree on the underlying forces behind these events. In this book José A. Scheinkman offers new insight into the mystery of bubbles. Noting some general characteristics of bubbles—such as the rise in trading volume and the coincidence between increases in supply and bubble implosions—Scheinkman offers a model, based on differences in beliefs among investors, that explains these observations.

Other top economists also offer their own thoughts on the issue: Sanford J. Grossman and Patrick Bolton expand on Scheinkman's discussion by looking at factors that contribute to bubbles—such as excessive leverage, overconfidence, mania, and panic in speculative markets—and Kenneth J. Arrow and Joseph E. Stiglitz contextualize Scheinkman's findings.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is Speculation, Trading, and Bubbles an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access Speculation, Trading, and Bubbles by José Scheinkman, Kenneth Arrow, Patrick Bolton, Joseph E. Stiglitz, Sanford Grossman in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Business & Business generale. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2014
ISBN
9780231537636
APPENDIX: A FORMAL MODEL
A.1 THE BASIC MODEL
I first exposit a simple model to illustrate the role of costly shorting and differences in beliefs in generating bubbles and the association between bubbles and trading. Consider four periods t = 1, 2, 3, 4; a single good; and a single risky asset in finite supply S. In addition to the risky asset, there also exists a risk-free technology. An investment of δ ≤ 1 units of the good in the risk-free technology at t yields one unit in period t + 1. Assume there are a large number of risk-neutral investors that only value consumption in the final period t = 4. Each investor is endowed with an amount W0 of the good.
The risky asset produces dividends at times t = 2, 3, 4. At each t = 2, 3, 4 each unit of the risky asset pays a dividend θt Єl, θh} with θh > θl. In what follows, I will refer to θhl) as the high (resp. low) dividend. Dividends at any t are independent of past and future dividends.1 The probability that θt = θl is .5, and we write
image
Assets are traded at t = 1, 2, 3, 4. If a dividend is paid in period t, trading occurs after the dividend is distributed—that is, the asset trades ex-dividend and the buyer of the asset in period t has the rights to all dividends from time t + 1 on. Thus in the final period t = 4, the price of the asset p4 = 0, since there are no dividends paid after period 4. The price at time t = 1, 2, 3 depends on the expectations of investors regarding the dividends to be paid in the future. We first calculate the willingness to pay of a “rational” risk-neutral investor that is not allowed to resell the asset after she buys it. Since the investor is risk-neutral, at time t = 3 she is willing to pay
image
for a unit of the asset. In the absence of resale opportunities, at t = 2, the rational investor is willing to pay
image
. Finally, at t = 1 that same rational investor with no resale opportunities would be willing to pay
image
In addition, we suppose that at each t = 1, 2, 3, a signal st is observed after the dividend at t (if t > 1) is observed but before trading occurs at t. Each signal st assumes one of three values {0, 1, 2}, is independent of past realizations of the signal and of the dividends, and has no predictive power for future dividends. Thus the signal st is pure noise. There are, however, two sets of investors, A and B. Each set has many investors. Agents in group A are rational and understand that the distribution of future dividends is independent of st. Agents in B actually believe that st predicts θt+1 and that the probability that θt+1 = θh given st is:
image
Thus agents in group B believe that the probability of a high dividend at t +1 increases with the observed st and that when st = 0(st = 2), θt+1 = θl(resp. θt+1 = θh) is more probable. All agents agree that st does not help predict θt+j for j≥2, and thus the only disagreement among investors is whether st can predict θt+1. To make agents in set B correct on average, and thus assure that ex-ante there are no optimistic or pessimistic investors, assume that the probability that st = 0 equals the probability that st = 2. Write q.<5 for this common probability, and observe that the probability that st = 1 is 1 − 2q>0.
In the case of binary random variables, forecasts have minimal precision2 when the probability of each realization is 1/2. This is exactly the forecast of rational agents here. Agents in group B, after observing st = 1, also have the same minimal forecast precision. However, if they observe st = 0 or st = 2 they employ forecasts that have higher precision, since they (mistakenly) believe that one of the two possible events has a probability of 3/4. In this sense agents in group B have an exaggerated view of the precision of their beliefs.
At time t = 3, rational agents in group A are wil...

Table of contents